Brouwer fixed point theorem

From Free net encyclopedia

(Redirected from Brouwer fixed-point theorem)

In mathematics, the Brouwer fixed point theorem states that every continuous function from the closed unit ball D n to itself has a fixed point. In this theorem, n is any positive integer, and the closed unit ball is the set of all points in Euclidean n-space Rn which are at distance at most 1 from the origin. Because the properties involved (continuity, being a fixed point) are invariant under homeomorphisms, the theorem equally applies if the domain is not the closed unit ball itself but some set homeomorphic to it (and therefore also closed, connected, without holes, etcetera).

The theorem has several "real world" illustrations. One works as follows: take two equal size sheets of graph paper with coordinate systems on them, lay one flat on the table and crumple up (but don't rip) the other one and place it any way you like on top of the first. Then there will be at least one point of the crumpled sheet that lies exactly on top of the corresponding point (i.e. the point with the same coordinates) of the flat sheet. This is a consequence of the n = 2 case of Brouwer's theorem applied to the continuous map that assigns to the coordinates of every point of the crumpled sheet the coordinates of the point of the flat sheet right beneath it. Yet another example: an informational display of a map in, for example, an airport terminal. The function that sends points in real space to their image on the map is continuous and therefore has a fixed point, usually indicated by a cross or arrow with the text You are here. A similar display outside the terminal would violate the condition that the function is "to itself" and fail to have a fixed point.

The Brouwer fixed point theorem was one of the early achievements of algebraic topology, and is the basis of more general fixed point theorems which are important in functional analysis. The case n = 3 was proved by L. E. J. Brouwer in 1909. Jacques Hadamard proved the general case in 1910, and Brouwer found a different proof in 1912. Since it must have an essentially non-constructive proof, it ran contrary to Brouwer's intuitionist ideals.

Contents

Proof outline

A full proof of the theorem would be too long to reproduce here, but the following paragraph outlines a proof omitting the difficult part. It is hoped that this will at least give some idea why the theorem might be expected to be true. Note that the boundary of D n is S n-1, the (n-1)-sphere.

Suppose f : D n → D n is a continuous function that has no fixed point. The idea is to show that this leads to a contradiction. For each x in D n, consider the straight line that passes through f(x) and x. There is only one such line, because f(x) ≠ x. Following this line from f(x) through x leads to a point on S n-1. Call this point g(x). This gives us a continuous function g : D n → S n-1. This is a special type of continuous function known as a retraction: every point of the codomain (in this case S n-1) is a fixed point of the function.

Intuitively it seems unlikely that there could be a retraction of D n onto S n-1, and in the case n = 1 it is obviously impossible because S 0 (i.e., the endpoints of the closed interval D 1) isn't even connected. The case n=2 takes more thought, but can be proven by using basic arguments involving the fundamental groups. For n > 2, however, proving the impossibility of the retraction is considerably more difficult. One way is to make use of homology groups: it can be shown that Hn-1(D n) is trivial while Hn-1(S n-1) is infinite cyclic. This shows that the retraction is impossible, because a retraction cannot increase the size of homology groups.

There is also an almost elementary combinatorial proof. Its main step consists in establishing Sperner's lemma in n dimensions.

There is also a quick proof, attributed to Morris Hirsch by John Milnor, based on the impossibility of a differentiable retraction. The proof starts by noting that the map f can be approximated by a smooth map retaining the property of not fixing a point; this can be done by using the Weierstrass approximation theorem, for example. One then defines a retraction as above which must now be differentiable. Such a retraction must have a non-singular value (by Sard's theorem), whose inverse image would be a 1-manifold with boundary. The boundary would have to contain at least two end points, both of which would have to lie on the boundary of the original ball--which would be impossible in a retraction!

A quite different proof given by David Gale is based on the game of Hex. The basic theorem about Hex is that no game can end in a draw. This is equivalent to the Brouwer fixed point theorem for dimension 2. By considering n-dimensional versions of Hex, one can prove in general that Brouwer's theorem is equivalent to the determinacy theorem for Hex.

Generalizations

External links

References

fr:Théorème du point fixe de Brouwer he:משפט נקודת השבת של ברואר it:Teorema del punto fisso di Brouwer nl:Vastepuntstelling van Brouwer sl:Brouwerjev izrek o negibni točki