Transfinite induction

From Free net encyclopedia

(Redirected from Transfinite recursion)

Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to (large) well-ordered sets, for instance to sets of ordinals or cardinals. It may be regarded as one of three forms of mathematical induction.

Contents

Transfinite induction

Suppose whenever for all α < β, P (α) is true, then P (β) is also true. Then transfinite induction tells us that P is true for all ordinals.

That is, if P(α) is true whenever P(β) is true for all β<α, then P(α) is true for all α. Or, more practically: in order to prove a property P for all ordinals α, one can assume that it is already known for all smaller β<α.

Usually the proof is broken down into three cases:

  • Zero case: Prove that P(0) is true.
  • Successor case: Prove that for any ordinal β, P (β+1) follows from P (β) or, if necessary, from P (β) together with for all α < β, P (α).
  • Limit case: Prove that for any limit ordinal λ, P (λ) follows from for all α < λ, P (α).

Transfinite recursion

Transfinite recursion is a method of constructing or defining something and is closely related to the concept of transfinite induction. As an example, a sequence of sets Aα is defined for every ordinal α, by specifying three things:

  • What A0 is
  • How to determine Aα+1 from Aα (or possibly from the entire sequence up to Aα)
  • For a limit ordinal λ, how to determine Aλ from the sequence of Aα for α < λ

Note that there's not much formal difference between the second and third clauses, but in practice they are so often different that it is useful to present them separately.

More generally, one can define objects by transfinite recursion on any well-founded relation R. (R need not even be a set; it can be a proper class, provided it is a set-like relation; that is, for any x, the collection of all y such that yRx must be a set.)

Relationship to AC

There is a popular misconception that transfinite induction, or transfinite recursion, or both, require the axiom of choice (AC). This is incorrect. However it is very often the case that proofs or constructions using the technique do use AC.

For example, consider the following construction of the Vitali set: First, wellorder the reals, say into a sequence <rα | α<c >, where c is the cardinality of the continuum. Let v0 equal r0. Then let v1 equal rα1, where α1 is least such that rα1 − v0 is not a rational number. Continue; at each step choose the least real from the r sequence that does not have a rational difference with any element thus far constructed in the v sequence. Continue until all the reals in the r sequence are exhausted. The final v sequence will enumerate the Vitali set.

The above argument uses AC in a blatant way at the very beginning, by wellordering the reals. Other uses are more subtle. For example, frequently a construction by transfinite recursion will not specify a unique value for Aα+1, given the sequence up to α, but will specify only a condition that Aα+1 must satisfy, and argue that it is possible to meet this condition. If it is not possible to define a unique example of such a set at each stage, then it may be necessary to invoke AC to choose one such at each step. For inductions/recursions of countable length, the weaker axiom of dependent choice, DC, is sufficient.

See also

it:Induzione transfinita ru:Трансфинитная индукция zh:超限归纳法