Contradiction

From Free net encyclopedia

Broadly speaking, a contradiction is an incompatibility between two or more statements, ideas, or actions. One must, it seems, reject at least one of the ideas outright.

In logic, contradiction is defined much more specifically, usually as the simultaneous assertion of a statement and its negation ("denial" can be used instead of "negation"). This, of course, assumes that "negation" has a non-problematic definition. This idea is based on Aristotle's law of non-contradiction which states that "One cannot say of something that it is and that it is not in the same respect and at the same time."

In TRIZ contradiction (as one of the basic definitions) is a situation where an attempt to improve one feature of the system causes deterioration of another feature (for example: If we want more acceleration, we need a larger engine - but that will increase the cost of the car).

In colloquial speech and in dialectical methodology, the word "contradiction" has a completely different meaning than in formal logic.

Contents

"Contradiction" outside of formal logic

In colloquial speech

In everyday speech, "contradiction" may be used in a much less rigorous way than in formal logic. For example, there is nothing logically contradictory involved in a man condemning the members of his church for not giving the church enough financial support even though he never puts anything in the collection plate when it goes around. In ordinary language we would be quite inclined to say that his actions contradict his words, but the immediate connection of this usage to the logical usage is unclear. Hypocrisy is certainly lamentable but it's hard to say that it's logically incoherent--our hypothetical church-goer, after all, is not clearly asserting anything by refusing to put money in the collection plate, let alone the logical negation of what he asserted.

One way to understand the colloquial usage might be to shift grounds from logical contradiction to what some philosophers describe as a performative contradiction. A hypocrite is not saying anything that contradicts the general principles that he asserts to be true; but his actions, in some sense, presuppose that those principles are false. Similarly, "I cannot assert anything." is a sentence that no-one can truly utter. This is not because of a logical contradiction in the sentence--it is, for example, true of the brain-dead. But there is a performative contradiction involved in the act of saying it; for to say it presupposes that you can assert something.

In Dialectics

Marxism

The meaning of "contradiction" in dialectical materialism pertains to the views of G.W.F. Hegel and Karl Marx. In this usage a "contradiction" does not refer to a conflict purely in a person's thinking or in logic, but indicates a clash between one's theory and one's practice, or one's words and one's deeds.

This meaning of contradiction is more of a practical, empirical, or real-world phenomenon than is meant by a logic-based contradiction. For Marx, capitalism involves a social system that has "contradictions" in the sense that the social classes have conflicting collective goals, and in the sense that even the ruling class of capitalists does not always attain their goals. In Marx's view, real-world contradictions are based in the social structure of the society in question, and inherently lead to class conflict, crisis, and eventually revolution where the existing order is overthrown and the formerly oppressed class rises up and assumes political power.

Liberalism

The idea of a contradiction as a conflict based in a social structure is not unique to Marxist thought. For liberal thinkers, the problem of public goods may be interpreted as a "contradiction" in that there is a conflict between what is good for society, i.e., the production of a public good, and what is good for individual free riders who refuse to pay the costs of the public good. This is one interpretation of Hegel's view of contradictions, seen for example in Paul Deising, Hegel's Dialectical Political Economy (ISBN 0813391318).

"Contradiction" in formal logic

Proof by contradiction

In deductive logic (and thus, also, in mathematics), a contradiction is usually taken as a sign that something has gone wrong, that you need to retrace the steps of your reasoning and "check your premises." This has been used to great effect in mathematics through the method of proof by contradiction: since a contradiction can never be true, it can thus never be the conclusion of a valid argument with all true premises. To construct a proof by contradiction, then, you construct a valid proof from a set of premises to a conclusion that is a logical contradiction. Since the conclusion is false, and the argument is valid, the only possibility is that one or more of the premises are false. This method is used in many key mathematical proofs, such as Euclid's proof that there is no greatest prime, and Cantor's diagonal proof that there are uncountably many real numbers between 0 and 1.

A paradox involving contradiction

Contradiction is associated with several notorious paradoxes. One of these is that in first-order predicate calculus any proposition (aka statement) can be derived from a contradiction. In other words, according to the predicate calculus, no matter what P and Q mean, if P and not-P are both true, then Q is true. In expression of this fact, contradictions are said to be "logically explosive" in first-order logic.

Thus, for example, the following argument is strictly valid, i.e. the premise logically entails the conclusion:

  1. Premise: 5 is both even and odd. (In our above formulation, this is P and not-P.)
  2. Conclusion: God exists. (This is Q.)

But atheists have no less reason to celebrate than theists, for this argument is also valid:

  1. Premise: 5 is both even and odd. (This is P and not-P.)
  2. Conclusion, God does not exist. (This is not-Q.)

Note that the premise shared by both arguments is incorrect; 5 is odd, but is not even. Therefore neither of these arguments are sound, which means neither gives a logical basis for believing its conclusion.

Nonetheless, perhaps most people find it odd that, if 5 were both even and odd, one could logically conclude anything about such an apparently unrelated matter as the existence of God. Stranger yet, the paradox implies that, if a person has any two beliefs that are contradictory, then that person is logically justified in any conceivable belief!

Proof of the paradox

Even though the basic rules of predicate calculus may each sound like good ways of reasoning, they collectively entail our paradox. Two ways of showing this follow.

The first way follows from the truth table definition of conjunction and implication:

  1. (P and ¬P) is false. (See the truth table entry for <math>P</math> ∧ <math>Q</math>.)
  2. Therefore, (P and ¬P) → Q is vacuously true. (See the truth table entry for <math>P</math> → <math>Q</math>.)

The second then, might interest those who find truth tables aesthetically flawed:

  1. Suppose P and ¬P. Under this assumption we can derive:
    1. P (Conjunction elimination)
    2. ¬P (Conjunction elimination)
    3. Suppose ¬Q. Under this assumption we can derive:
      1. P (Copying from above)
    4. Thus ¬Q → P (Conditional proof)
    5. ¬P → Q (Contrapositive of previous line)
    6. Q (Modus ponens)
  2. Thus (P and ¬P) → Q (Conditional proof)

Contradictions and philosophy

Coherentism is an epistemological theory in which a belief is justified based at least in part on being part of a non-contradictory system of beliefs. ("Contradictory" here is almost always taken in the formal logic sense.)

Meta-contradiction

It often occurs in philosophy that the presence of the argument contradicts with the claims of the argument. An example of this is when Heraclitus says that knowledge is impossible, or arguably when Nietzsche says that you should not obey others, you should not be obeying his statement. There are many similar examples. Often coherentism is temporarily ignored for these theories, and a relief is granted to the philosophers because there is no other way to explain the theory.

See also

fr:Contradiction ko:모순 is:Mótsögn lt:Prieštaravimas nl:Contradictie ja:矛盾 pt:Contradição ru:Противоречие (ТРИЗ) sv:Motsägelse zh:矛盾