Fundamental theorem of algebra

From Free net encyclopedia

In mathematics, the fundamental theorem of algebra states that every complex polynomial <math>p(z)</math> in one variable and of degree <math>n</math> ≥ <math>1</math> has some complex root. In other words, the field of complex numbers is algebraically closed and therefore, as for any other algebraically closed field, the equation <math>p(z)=0</math> has <math>n</math> roots (not necessarily distinct).

The name of the theorem is now considered something of a misnomer by many mathematicians, since it is not fundamental for contemporary algebra.

Contents

History

Peter Rothe (Petrus Roth), in his book Arithmetica Philosophica (published in 1608), wrote that a polynomial equation of degree <math>n</math> (with real coefficients) may have <math>n</math> solutions. Albert Girard, in his book L'invention nouvelle en l'Algèbre (published in 1629), asserted that a polynomial equation of degree <math>n</math> has <math>n</math> solutions, but he did not state that they had to be complex numbers. Furthermore, he added that his assertion holds “unless the equation is incomplete”, by which he meant that no coefficient is equal to <math>0</math>. However, when he explains in detail what he means, it is clear that he actually believes that his assertion is always true; for instance, he shows that the equation <math>x^4=4x-3</math>, although incomplete, has four solutions: <math>1</math>, <math>1</math>, <math>-1+i</math>√<math>2</math>, and <math>-1-i</math>√<math>2</math>.

As will be mentioned again below, it follows from the fundamental theorem of algebra that every polynomial with real coefficients and degree greater than <math>0</math> can be written as a product of polynomials with real coefficients whose degree is either <math>1</math> or <math>2</math>. However, in 1702 Leibniz said that no polynomial of the type <math>x^4+a^4</math> (with <math>a</math> real and distinct from <math>0</math>) can be written in such a way. Later, Nikolaus Bernoulli made the same assertion concerning the polynomial <math>x^4-4x^3+2x^2+4x+4</math>, but he got a letter from Euler in 1742 in which he was told that his polynomial happened to be equal to

<math>(x^2-(2+\alpha)x+1+\sqrt{7}+\alpha)(x^2-(2-\alpha)x+1+\sqrt{7}-\alpha),\,</math>

where <math>\alpha</math> is the square root of <math>4+2</math>√<math>7</math>, whereas

<math>x^4+a^4=(x^2+a\sqrt{2}x+a^2)(x^2-a\sqrt{2}x+a^2).\,</math>

A first attempt at proving the theorem was made by d'Alembert in 1746, but his proof was incomplete. Among other problems, it assumed implicitly a theorem (now known as Puiseux's theorem) which would be proved only more than a century later (and furthermore the proof assumed the fundamental theorem of algebra). Other attempts were made by Euler (1749), de Foncenex (1759), Lagrange (1772), and Laplace (1795). These last four attempts assumed implicitly Girard's assertion; to be more precise, the existence of solutions was assumed and all that remained to be proved was that their form was <math>a+bi</math> for some real numbers <math>a</math> and <math>b</math>. In modern terms, Euler, de Foncenex, Lagrange, and Laplace were assuming the existence of a splitting field of the polynomial <math>p(z)</math>.

At the end of the 18th century two new proofs were published which did not assume the existence of roots. One of them, due to James Wood and mainly algebraic, was published in 1798 and it was totally ignored. Wood's proof had an algebraic gap. The other one was published by Gauss in 1799 and it was mainly geometric, but it had a topological gap. A rigorous proof was published by Argand in 1806; it was here that, for the first time, the fundamental theorem of algebra was stated for polynomials with complex coefficients, rather than just real coefficients. Gauss produced two other proofs in 1816 and another version of his original proof in 1849.

The first textbook containing a proof of the theorem was Cauchy's Cours d'analyse de l'École Royale Polytechnique (1821). It contained Argand's proof, although Argand is not credited for it.

None of the proofs mentioned so far is constructive. It was Weierstrass who raised for the first time, in 1891, the problem of finding a constructive proof of the fundamental theorem of algebra. Such a proof was obtained by Hellmuth Kneser in 1940 and simplified by his son Martin Kneser in 1981.

Proofs

All proofs of the fundamental theorem involve some analysis, or more precisely, the concept of continuity of real or complex functions. Some proofs also use differentiable or even analytic functions.

Some proofs of the theorem only prove that any polynomial with real coefficients has some complex root. This is enough to establish the theorem in the general case because, given a polynomial <math>p(z)</math> with complex coefficients, the polynomial <math>q(z)=p(z)\overline{p(\overline{z})}</math> has only real coefficients and, if <math>z</math> is a zero of <math>q(z)</math>, then either <math>z</math> or its conjugate is a root of <math>p(z)</math>.

A large number of non-algebraic proofs of the theorem use the fact (sometimes called “growth lemma”) that <math>p(z)</math> behaves like <math>z^n</math> when <math>|z|</math> is large enough. A more precise statement is: there is some positive real number <math>R</math> such that

<math>|z|^n/2<|p(z)|<3|z|^n/2</math>

when <math>|z|>R</math>.

We mention approaches via complex analysis, topology, and algebra:

Analytical proofs

Find a closed disk <math>D</math> of radius <math>r</math> centered at the origin such that <math>|p(z)|>|p(0)|</math> whenever <math>|z|</math>≥ <math>r</math>. The minimum of <math>|p(z)|</math> on <math>D</math>, which must exist since <math>D</math> is compact, is therefore achieved at some point <math>z_0</math> in the interior of <math>D</math>, but not at any point of its boundary. The minimum modulus principle implies then that <math>p(z_0)=0</math>. In other words, <math>z_0</math> is a zero of <math>p(z)</math>.

Another analytical proof can be obtained along this line of thought observing that, since <math>|p(z)|>|p(0)|</math> outside <math>D</math>, the minimum of <math>|p(z)|</math> on the whole complex plane is achieved at <math>z_0</math>. If <math>|p(z_0)|>0</math>, then <math>1/p</math> is a bounded holomorphic function in the entire complex plane since, for each complex number <math>z</math>, <math>|1/p(z)|</math>≤<math>|1/p(z_0)|</math>. Applying Liouville's theorem, which states that a bounded entire function must be constant, we conclude that <math>1/p</math> is constant and therefore that <math>p</math> is constant.

Topological proofs

As an alternative to the use of Liouville's theorem in the previous proof, we can write <math>p(z)</math> as a polynomial in <math>z-z_0</math>: there is some natural number <math>k</math> and there are some complex numbers <math>c_k</math>, <math>c_{k+1},</math> … , <math>c_n</math> such that <math>c_k</math> ≠ 0 and that

<math>p(z)=p(z_0)+c_k(z-z_0)^k+c_{k+1}(z-z_0)^{k+1}+</math> ···<math>+c_n(z-z_0)^n</math>.

It follows that if <math>a</math> is a <math>k</math>th root of <math>-p(z_0)/c_k</math> and if <math>t</math> is positive and sufficiently small, then <math>|p(z_0+ta)|<|p(z_0)|</math>, which is impossible, since <math>|p(z_0)|</math> is the minimum of <math>|p|</math> on <math>D</math>.

For another topological proof by contradiction, assume <math>p(z)</math> has no zeros. Choose a large positive number <math>R</math> such that, for <math>|z|=R</math>, the leading term <math>z^n</math> of <math>p(z)</math> dominates all other terms combined; in other words, such that <math>|z|^n>|a_{n-1}z^{n-1}+</math> ··· <math>+a_0|</math>. As <math>z</math> traverses the circle <math>|z|=R</math> once counter-clockwise, <math>p(z)</math>, like <math>z^n</math>, winds <math>n</math> times counter-clockwise around <math>0</math>. At the other extreme, with <math>|z|=0</math>, the “curve” <math>p(z)</math> is simply the single (nonzero) point <math>p(0)</math>, whose winding number is clearly <math>0</math>. If the loop followed by <math>z</math> is continuously deformed between these extremes, the path of <math>p(z)</math> also deforms continuously. Since <math>p(z)</math> has no zeros, the path can never cross over <math>0</math> as it deforms, and hence its winding number with respect to <math>0</math> will never change. However, given that the winding number started as <math>n</math> and ended as <math>0</math>, this is absurd. Therefore, <math>p(z)</math> has at least one zero.

Algebraic proof

This proof uses only two facts about real numbers whose proof require analysis (more precisely, the intermediate value theorem), namely:

  • every polynomial with odd degree and real coefficients has some real root;
  • every non-negative real number has a square root.

It follows from the second assertion that, if <math>a</math> and <math>b</math> are real numbers, then there are complex numbers <math>z_1</math> and <math>z_2</math> such that the polynomial <math>z^2+az+b</math> is equal to <math>(z-z_1)(z-z_2)</math>.

As it was mentioned above, it suffices to check that the fundamental theorem is true for all polynomials <math>p(z)</math> with real coefficients. The theorem can be proved by induction on the greatest non-negative integer <math>k</math> such that <math>2^k</math> divides the degree <math>n</math> of <math>p(z)</math>. Let <math>F</math> be a splitting field of <math>p(z)</math> (seen as a polynomial with complex coefficients); in other words, the field <math>F</math> contains C and there are elements <math>z_1</math>, <math>z_2</math>, …, <math>z_n</math> in <math>F</math> such that

<math>p(z)=(z-z_1)(z-z_2)</math> ··· <math>(z-z_n)</math>.

If <math>k=0</math>, then <math>n</math> is odd, and therefore <math>p(z)</math> has a real root. Now, suppose that <math>n=2^km</math> (with <math>m</math> odd and <math>k>0</math>) and that the theorem is already proved when the degree of the polynomial has the form <math>2^{k-1}m'</math> with <math>m'</math> odd. For a real number <math>t</math>, define:

<math>q_t(z)=\prod_{1\le i<j\le n}\left(z-z_i-z_j-tz_iz_j\right).\,</math>

Then the coefficients of <math>q_t(z)</math> are symmetric polynomials in the <math>z_i</math>'s with real coefficients. Therefore, they can be expressed as polynomials with real coefficients in the elementary symmetric polynomials, that is, in <math>-a_1, a_2, \dots, (-1)^na_n</math>. So <math>q_t</math> has in fact real coefficients. Furthermore, the degree of <math>q_t</math> is <math>n(n-1)/2=2^{k-1}m(n-1)</math>, and <math>m(n-1)</math> is an odd number. So, using the induction hypothesis, <math>q_t</math> has, at least, one real root; in other words, <math>z_i+z_j+tz_iz_j</math> is real for two distinct elements <math>i</math> and <math>j</math> from {<math>1,\dots,n</math>}. Since there are more real numbers than pairs <math>(i,j)</math>, one can find distinct real numbers <math>t</math> and <math>s</math> such that <math>z_i+z_j+tz_iz_j</math> and <math>z_i+z_j+sz_iz_j</math> are real (for the same <math>i</math> and <math>j</math>). So, both <math>z_i+z_j</math> and <math>z_iz_j</math> are real numbers, and therefore <math>z_i</math> and <math>z_j</math> are complex numbers, since they are roots of the polynomial <math>z^2-(z_1+z_2)z+z_1z_2</math>.

Corollaries

Since the fundamental theorem of algebra can be seen as the statement that the field of complex numbers is algebraically closed, it follows that any theorem concerning algebraically closed fields applies to the field of complex numbers. Here are a few more consequences of the theorem, which are either about the field of real numbers or about the relationship between the field of real numbers and the field of complex numbers:

  • The field of complex numbers is the algebraic closure of the field of real numbers.
  • Every polynomial in one variable <math>x</math> with real coefficients is the product of a constant, polynomials of the form <math>x+a</math> with <math>a</math> real, and polynomials of the form <math>x^2+ax+b</math> with <math>a</math> and <math>b</math> real and <math>a^2-4b<0</math> (which is the same thing as saying that the polynomial <math>x^2+ax+b</math> has no real roots).
  • Every rational function in one variable <math>x</math>, with real coefficients, can be written as the sum of a polynomial function with rational functions of the form <math>a/(x-b)^n</math> (where <math>n</math> is a natural number, and <math>a</math> and <math>b</math> are real numbers), and rational functions of the form <math>(ax+b)/(x^2+cx+d)^n</math> (where <math>n</math> is a natural number, and <math>a</math>, <math>b</math>, <math>c</math>, and <math>d</math> are real numbers such that <math>c^2-4d<0</math>). A corollary of this is that every rational function in one variable and real coefficients has an elementary primitive.
  • Every algebraic extension of the real field is isomorphic either to the real field or to the complex field.

References

  • A.-L. Cauchy, Cours d'Analyse de l'École Royale Polytechnique, 1ère partie: Analyse Algébrique, 1992, Éditions Jacques Gabay, ISBN 2-87647-053-5
  • B. Fine and G. Rosenberger, The Fundamental Theorem of Algebra, 1997, Springer-Verlag, ISBN 0-387-94657-8
  • C. Gilain, “Sur l'histoire du théorème fondamental de l'algèbre: théorie des équations et calcul intégral”, Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 42 (1991), 91–136
  • E. Netto and R. Le Vavasseur, “Les fonctions rationnelles §80–88: Le théorème fondamental”, in Encyclopédie des Sciences Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées, tome I, vol. 2, 1992, Éditions Jacques Gabay, ISBN 2-87647-101-9
  • R. Remmert, “The Fundamental Theorem of Algebra”, in Numbers, 1991, Springer-Verlag, ISBN 0-387-97497-0
  • D. E. Smith, “A Source Book in Mathematics”, 1959, Dover Publications, ISBN 0-486-64690-4

ca:Teorema fonamental de l'àlgebra da:Algebraens fundamentalsætning de:Fundamentalsatz der Algebra es:Teorema fundamental del álgebra fa:قضیه اساسی جبر fr:Théorème de d'Alembert-Gauss ko:대수학의 기본 정리 it:Teorema fondamentale dell'algebra he:המשפט היסודי של האלגברה nl:Hoofdstelling van de algebra ja:代数学の基本定理 pl:Zasadnicze twierdzenie algebry pt:Teorema fundamental da álgebra ru:Основная теорема алгебры sk:Základná veta algebry sl:Osnovni izrek algebre fi:Algebran peruslause sv:Algebrans fundamentalsats th:ทฤษฎีบทมูลฐานของพีชคณิต tr:Cebirin Temel Teoremi zh:代数基本定理