Irrational number
From Free net encyclopedia
In mathematics, an irrational number is any real number that is not a rational number, i.e., one that cannot be written as a ratio of two integers, i.e., it is not of the form
- <math>\frac{a}{b}</math>
where a and b are integers and b is not zero. It can readily be shown that the irrational numbers are precisely those numbers whose expansion in any given base (decimal, binary, etc) never ends and never enters a periodic pattern, but no mathematician takes that to be a definition. Almost all real numbers are irrational, in a sense which is defined more precisely below.
Some irrational numbers are algebraic numbers, such as √2, the square root of two, and 3√5, the cube root of 5, and the golden ratio, symbolized by the Greek letter <math>\varphi</math> (phi) or less commonly by <math>\tau</math> (tau); others are transcendental numbers such as π and e.
When the ratio of lengths of two line segments is irrational, the line segments are also described as being incommensurable, meaning they share no measure in common. A measure of a line segment I in this sense is a line segment J that "measures" I in the sense that some whole number of copies of J laid end-to-end occupy the same length as I.
Contents |
History
The earliest known use of irrational numbers was in the Indian Sulba Sutras composed between 800-500 BC. The first proof of irrational numbers is usually attributed to Pythagoras, more specifically to the Pythagorean Hippasus of Metapontum, who produced a (most likely geometrical) proof of the irrationality of the square root of 2. The story goes that Hippasus discovered irrational numbers when trying to represent the square root of 2 as a fraction (proof below). However Pythagoras believed in the absoluteness of numbers, and could not accept the existence of irrational numbers. He could not disprove their existence through logic, but his beliefs would not accept the existence of irrational numbers and so he sentenced Hippasus to death by drowning. Later Greek mathematicians, such as Theaetetus and Eudoxus worked with other quadratic irrationalities. Euclid's Elements Book 10 is dedicated to classification of irrational magnitudes.
The sixteenth century saw the final acceptance of negative, integral and fractional numbers. The seventeenth century saw decimal fractions with the modern notation quite generally used by mathematicians. The next hundred years saw the imaginary become a powerful tool in the hands of Abraham de Moivre, and especially of Leonhard Euler. For the nineteenth century it remained to complete the theory of complex numbers, to separate irrationals into algebraic and transcendental, to prove the existence of transcendental numbers, and to make a scientific study of a subject which had remained almost dormant since Euclid, the theory of irrationals. The year 1872 saw the publication of the theories of Karl Weierstrass (by his pupil Kossak), Heine (Crelle, 74), Georg Cantor (Annalen, 5), and Richard Dedekind. Méray had taken in 1869 the same point of departure as Heine, but the theory is generally referred to the year 1872. Weierstrass's method has been completely set forth by Pincherle (1880), and Dedekind's has received additional prominence through the author's later work (1888) and the recent endorsement by Paul Tannery (1894). Weierstrass, Cantor, and Heine base their theories on infinite series, while Dedekind founds his on the idea of a cut (Schnitt) in the system of real numbers, separating all rational numbers into two groups having certain characteristic properties. The subject has received later contributions at the hands of Weierstrass, Kronecker (Crelle, 101), and Méray.
Continued fractions, closely related to irrational numbers (and due to Cataldi, 1613), received attention at the hands of Euler, and at the opening of the nineteenth century were brought into prominence through the writings of Joseph Louis Lagrange. Other noteworthy contributions have been made by Druckenmüller (1837), Kunze (1857), Lemke (1870), and Günther (1872). Ramus (1855) first connected the subject with determinants, resulting, with the subsequent contributions of Heine, Möbius, and Günther, in the theory of Kettenbruchdeterminanten. Dirichlet also added to the general theory, as have numerous contributors to the applications of the subject.
Lambert proved (1761) that π cannot be rational, and that en is irrational if n is rational (unless n = 0), a proof, however, which left much to be desired. Legendre (1794) completed Lambert's proof, and showed that π is not the square root of a rational number. Paolo Ruffini (1799) first proof, (largely ignored) of Abel–Ruffini theorem that the general quintic or higher equations cannot be solved by a general formula involving only arithmetical operations and roots. Évariste Galois (1831) sends a memoir to the French Academy of Science: On the condition of solvability of equations by radicals, later developed into Galois theory which has been central to the proof that π and e are transcendental. Joseph Liouville (1840) showed that neither e nor e2 can be a root of an integral quadratic equation. Niels Henrik Abel (1842) partially proves the Abel–Ruffini theorem. The existence of transcendental numbers was first established by Liouville (1844, 1851), the proof being subsequently displaced by Georg Cantor (1873). Charles Hermite (1873) first proved <math>e</math> transcendental, and Ferdinand von Lindemann (1882), starting from Hermite's conclusions, showed the same for π. Lindemann's proof was much simplified by Weierstrass (1885), still further by David Hilbert (1893), and has finally been made elementary by Adolf Hurwitz and Paul Albert Gordan.
Example proofs
The square root of 2
One proof of the irrationality of the square root of 2 is the following reductio ad absurdum. The proposition is proved by assuming the negation and showing that that leads to a contradiction, which means that the proposition must be true.
- Assume that √2 is a rational number. This would mean that there exist integers a and b such that a / b = √2.
- Then √2 can be written as an irreducible fraction (the fraction is shortened as much as possible) a / b such that a and b are coprime integers and (a / b)2 = 2.
- It follows that a2 / b2 = 2 and a2 = 2 b2.
- Therefore a2 is even because it is equal to 2 b2 which is obviously even.
- It follows that a must be even. (Odd numbers have odd squares and even numbers have even squares.)
- Because a is even, there exists a k that fulfills: a = 2k.
- We insert the last equation of (3) in (6): (2k)2 = 2b2 is equivalent to 4k2 = 2b2 is equivalent to 2k2 = b2.
- Because 2k2 is even it follows that b2 is also even which means that b is even because only even numbers have even squares.
- By (5) and (8) a and b are both even, which contradicts that a / b is irreducible as stated in (2).
Since we have found a contradiction the assumption (1) that √2 is a rational number must be false. The opposite is proven. √2 is irrational.
This proof can be generalized to show that any root of any natural number is either a natural number or irrational.
Another proof
Another reductio ad absurdum argument showing that √2 is irrational is less well-known:
- Assume that √2 is a rational number. This would mean that there exist integers m and n such that m / n = √2.
- By substitution, it can be shown that √2 = (2n - m)/(m - n).
- Since √2 > 1, it follows that m > n, and it can be shown that m > 2n - m
So a fraction in lowest terms is reduced to yet lower terms. That is a contradiction if n and m are positive integers, so the assumption that √2 is rational must be false.
Similarly, assume an isosceles right triangle whose leg and hypotenuse have respective integer lengths n and m. By the Pythagorean theorem, the ratio m/n equals √2. It is possible to construct by a classic compass and straightedge construction a smaller isosceles right triangle whose leg and hypotenuse have respective lengths m - n and 2n - m. That construction proves the irrationality of √2 by the kind of method that was employed by ancient Greek geometers.
The golden ratio
When a line segment is divided into two disjoint subsegments in such a way that the ratio of the whole to the longer part equals the ratio of the longer part to the shorter part, then that ratio is the golden ratio, equal to
- <math>\varphi={1+\sqrt{5} \over 2}.</math>
Assume this is a rational number n/m in lowest terms. Take n to be the length of the whole and m the length of the longer part. Then the length of the shorter part is n − m. Then we have
- <math>{n \over m}={\mathrm{whole} \over \mathrm{longer}\ \mathrm{part}}
={\mathrm{longer}\ \mathrm{part} \over \mathrm{shorter}\ \mathrm{part}} ={m \over n-m}.</math>
But this puts a fraction already in lowest terms into lower terms—a contradiction. Therefore the initial assumption that φ is rational is false.
Logarithms
Perhaps the numbers most easily proved to be irrational are certain logarithms. Here is a proof by reductio ad absurdum that log23 is irrational:
- Assume log23 is rational. For some positive integers m and n, we have log23 = m/n.
- It follows that 2m/n = 3.
- Raise each side to the n power, find 2m = 3n.
- But 2 to any integer power greater than 0 is even (because at least one of its prime factors is 2) and 3 to any integer power greater than 0 is odd (because none of its prime factors is 2), so the original assumption is false.
Similar cases such as log102 can be treated similarly.
Transcendental and algebraic irrationals
Almost all irrational numbers are transcendental and all transcendental numbers are irrational: the article on transcendental numbers lists several examples. er and πr are irrational if r ≠ 0 is rational; eπ is also irrational.
Another way to construct irrational numbers is as irrational algebraic numbers, i.e. as zeros of polynomials with integer coefficients: start with a polynomial equation
- p(x) = an xn + an-1 xn−1 + ... + a1 x + a0 = 0
where the coefficients ai are integers. Suppose you know that there exists some real number x with p(x) = 0 (for instance if n is odd and an is non-zero, then because of the intermediate value theorem). The only possible rational roots of this polynomial equation are of the form r/s where r is a divisor of a0 and s is a divisor of an; there are only finitely many such candidates which you can all check by hand. If neither of them is a root of p, then x must be irrational. For example, this technique can be used to show that x = (21/2 + 1)1/3 is irrational: we have (x3 − 1)2 = 2 and hence x6 − 2x3 − 1 = 0, and this latter polynomial does not have any rational roots (the only candidates to check are ±1).
Because the algebraic numbers form a field, many irrational numbers can be constructed by combining transcendental and algebraic numbers. For example 3π+2, π + √2 and e√3 are irrational (and even transcendental).
Decimal expansions
It is often erroneously assumed that mathematicians define "irrational number" in terms of decimal expansions, calling a number irrational if its decimal expansion neither repeats nor terminates. No mathematician takes that to be the definition, since the choice of base 10 would be arbitrary and since the standard definition is simpler and more well-motivated. Nonetheless it is true that a number is of the form n/m where n and m are integers, if and only if its decimal expansion repeats or terminates. When the long division algorithm that everyone learns in school is applied to the division of n by m, only m remainders are possible. If 0 appears as a remainder, the decimal expansion terminates. If 0 never occurs, then the algorithm can run at most m − 1 steps without using any remainder more than once. After that, a remainder must recur, and then the decimal expansion repeats! Conversely, suppose we are faced with a recurring decimal, for example:
- <math>A=0.7\,162\,162\,162\,\dots</math>
Since the length of the repitend is 3, multiply by 103:
- <math>1000A=7\,16.2\,162\,162\,\dots</math>
and then subtract A from both sides:
- <math>999A=715.5\,.</math>
Then
- <math>A=\frac{715.5}{999}=\frac{7155}{9990}=\frac{135\times 53}{135\times 74}=\frac{53}{74}.</math>
(The "135" above can be found quickly via Euclid's algorithm.)
Open questions
It is not known whether π + e and π − e are irrational or not. In fact, there is no pair of non-zero integers m and n for which it is known whether mπ + ne is irrational or not. It is not known whether 2e, πe, <math>\pi^\sqrt{2}</math>, Catalan's constant, or the Euler-Mascheroni gamma constant γ are irrational.
The set of all irrationals
The set of all irrational numbers is uncountable (since the rationals are countable and the reals are uncountable). The set of algebraic irrationals, that is, the non-transcendental irrationals, is countable. Using the absolute value to measure distances, the irrational numbers become a metric space which is not complete. However, this metric space is homeomorphic to the complete metric space of all sequences of positive integers; the homeomorphism is given by the infinite continued fraction expansion. This shows that the Baire category theorem applies to the space of irrational numbers.
External links
bn:অমূলদ সংখ্যা ca:Nombre irracional cs:Iracionální číslo da:Irrationale tal de:Irrationale Zahl es:Número irracional eo:Neracionala nombro fa:اعداد گنگ fr:Nombre irrationnel gl:Número irracional ko:무리수 hr:Iracionalni brojevi is:Óræðar tölur it:Numero irrazionale he:מספר אי רציונלי la:Numerus irrationalis lt:Iracionalusis skaičius nl:Irrationaal getal ja:無理数 no:Irrasjonalt tall nn:Irrasjonalt tal pl:Liczby niewymierne pt:Número irracional ru:Иррациональное число scn:Nùmmuru irrazziunali sl:Iracionalno število sr:Ирационалан број fi:Irrationaaliluku sv:Irrationella tal th:จำนวนอตรรกยะ tr:İrrasyonel sayılar zh:無理數