Stark–Heegner theorem

From Free net encyclopedia

(Difference between revisions)

Current revision

In number theory, the Stark–Heegner theorem states precisely which quadratic imaginary number fields admit unique factorisation in their ring of integers. It solves a special case of Gauss's class number problem of determining the number of imaginary quadratic fields that have a given fixed class number.

Let Q denote the set of rational numbers, and let d be a square-free integer (i.e., a product of distinct primes) other than 1. Then Q(√ d) is a finite extension of Q, called a quadratic extension. The class number of Q(√ d) is the number of equivalence classes of ideals of Q(√ d), where two ideals I and J are equivalent if and only if there exist principal ideals (a) and (b) such that (a)I = (b)J. Thus, Q(√ d) is a principal ideal domain (and hence a unique factorization domain) if and only if the class number of Q(√ d) is equal to 1. The Stark-Heegner theorem can then be stated as follows:

If d < 0, then the class number of Q(√ d) is equal to 1 if and only if d = −1, −2, −3, −7, −11, −19, −43, −67, or −163.

This result was first conjectured by Gauss and proven by Kurt Heegner in 1952, although Heegner's proof was not accepted until Harold Stark gave a proof in 1967, which Stark showed was actually equivalent to Heegner's.

If, on the other hand, d > 0, then it is unknown whether there are infinitely many fields Q(√ d) with class number 1. Computational results indicate that there are a great many such fields to say the least.

References

Dorian Goldfeld: The Gauss Class Number Problem For Imaginary Quadratic Fieldsfr:Théorème de Stark-Heegner