Fundamental theorem of arithmetic

From Free net encyclopedia

Template:Inappropriate person In mathematics, and in particular number theory, the fundamental theorem of arithmetic (or unique factorization theorem) states that every natural number greater than one either is itself a prime number or can be written as a product of prime numbers. For instance, consider the following prime factorization of 6936 and 1200:

  • <math>6936 = 2^3 \cdot 3 \cdot 17^2</math>
  • <math>1200 = 2^4 \cdot 3 \cdot 5^2</math>

There are no other possible factorizations of 6936 or 1200 into prime numbers. The above representation collapses multiple prime factors (namely 2, 17 and 5) into powers for easier identification. Because multiplication is commutative, the order of factors is irrelevant and usually written from smallest to largest.

While the value one is not itself prime, it is the product of no numbers by the empty product rule.

Contents

Applications

The fundamental theorem of arithmetic establishes the importance of prime numbers. Prime numbers are the basic building blocks of any positive integer, in the sense that each positive integer can be constructed from primes with one unique construction. Finding the prime factorization of an integer allows derivation of all its' divisors, both prime and non-prime.

For example, the above factorization of 6936 shows that any positive divisor of 6936 must have the form 2a<math>\cdot</math>3b<math>\cdot</math>17c, where a takes one of the 4 values in {0, 1, 2, 3}, where b takes one of the 2 values in {0, 1}, and where c takes one of the 3 values in {0, 1, 2}. Multiplying the numbers of independent options together produces a total of 4<math>\cdot</math>2<math>\cdot</math>3 = 24 positive divisors.

Once the prime factorizations of two numbers are known, their greatest common divisor and least common multiple can be found quickly. For instance, from the above it is shown that the greatest common divisor of 6936 and 1200 is 23<math>\cdot</math> 3 = 24. However if the prime factorizations are not known, the use of the Euclidean algorithm generally requires much less calculation than factoring the two numbers.

The fundamental theorem ensures that additive and multiplicative arithmetic functions are completely determined by their values on the powers of prime numbers.

Proof

The theorem was essentially first proved by Euclid, but the first full and correct proof is found in the Disquisitiones Arithmeticae by Carl Friedrich Gauss.

Although at first sight it seems 'obvious', it does not hold in more general number systems, including many rings of algebraic integers. This was first pointed out by Ernst Kummer in 1843, in his work on Fermat's last theorem. The recognition of this failure is one of the earliest developments in algebraic number theory.

Euclid's Proof

The proof consists of two steps. In the first step every number is shown to be a product of zero or more primes. In the second, the proof shows that any two representations may be unified into a single representation.

Non-prime composite numbers

Suppose there were a positive integer which cannot be written as a product of primes. Then there must be a smallest such number: let it be n. This number n cannot be 1, because of the convention above. It cannot be a prime number either, since any prime number is a product of a single prime, itself. So it must be a composite number. Thus

n = ab

where both a and b are positive integers smaller than n. Since n was the smallest number for which the theorem fails, both a and b can be written as products of primes. But then

n = ab

can be written as a product of primes as well, a contradiction. This is a minimal counterexample argument.

Unique Composition

The uniqueness part of the proof hinges on the following fact: if a prime number p divides a product ab, then it divides a or it divides b (Euclid's lemma). This is a lemma, to prove first. For that, if p doesn't divide a, then p and a are coprime and Bézout's identity yields integers x and y such that

px + ay = 1.

Multiplying with b yields

pbx + aby = b,

and since both summands on the left-hand side are divisible by p, the right-hand side is also divisible by p. That proves the lemma.

Now take two products of primes which are equal. Take any prime p from the first product. It divides the first product, and hence also the second. By the above fact, p must then divide at least one factor in the second product. But the factors are all primes themselves, so p must actually be equal to one of the factors of the second product. So p can be cancelled from both products. Continuing in this fashion, eventually the prime factors of the two products must match up precisely.

Proof by Infinite Descent

Another proof of the uniqueness of the prime factorization of a given integer uses infinite descent: Assume that a certain integer can be written as (at least) two different products of prime numbers, then there must exist a smallest integer s with such a property. Call the two products of s p1 ... pm and q1 ... qn. No pi (with 1 ≤ im) can be equal to any qj (with 1 ≤ jn), as there would otherwise be a smaller integer factorizable in two ways (by removing prime factors common in both products) violating the above assumption. Now it can be assumed without loss of generality that p1 is a prime factor smaller than any qj (with 1 ≤ jn). Take q1. Then there exist integers d and r such that

q1/p1 = d + r/p1

and 0 < r < p1 < q1 (r can't be 0, as that would make q1 a multiple of p1 and not prime). The result is that

p2 ... pm = (d + r/p1) q2 ... qn = dq2 ... qn + rq2 ... qn/p1.

The second term in the last expression must be equal to an integer, which can be called k, i.e.

k = rq2 ... qn/p1.

This gives

p1k = rq2 ... qn.

The value of both sides of this equation is obviously smaller than s, but is still large enough to be factorizable. Since r is smaller than p1, the two prime factorizations we get on each side after both k and r are written out as their product of primes must be different. This is in contradiction with s being the smallest integer factorizable in more than one way. Thus the original assumption must be false.

Bourbaki's proof by abstract algebra

This proof requires an initial existence proof for a composition series for the group Z/(a) and shows that all of the its terms have the form Z/(p) for some prime number p. Since the order of Z/(a) is equal to the product of the orders of the factors in the composition series, this gives a factorization of a into prime numbers. Then the Jordan-Hölder theorem is established. This guarantees the uniqueness of the composition series, and hence the uniqueness of the prime factorization. This is the approach used by Nicolas Bourbaki's Algebra.

References

Bibliography

  • Baker, Alan, A Concise Introduction to the Theory of Numbers, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1984). ISBN 0521286549.

See also

External links

ca:Teorema fonamental de l'aritmètica da:Aritmetikkens fundamentalsætning de:Fundamentalsatz der Arithmetik el:Θεμελιώδες θεώρημα της αριθμητικής es:Teorema fundamental de la Aritmética fa:قضیه اساسی حساب fr:Théorème fondamental de l'arithmétique ko:정수론의 기본 정리 it:Teorema fondamentale dell'aritmetica he:המשפט היסודי של האריתמטיקה hu:A számelmélet alaptétele nl:Hoofdstelling van de rekenkunde pl:Podstawowe twierdzenie arytmetyki pt:Teorema fundamental da aritmética ru:Основная теорема арифметики simple:Fundamental theorem of arithmetic sl:Osnovni izrek aritmetike sr:Основна теорема аритметике th:ทฤษฎีบทมูลฐานของเลขคณิต tr:Aritmetiğin Temel Teoremi zh:算术基本定理